Covariance temporal precedence and an absence of alternative explanations are all criteria for

Introduction

Without respect to a given statistical model, mediation processes are framed in terms of intermediate variables between an independent variable and a dependent variable, with a minimum of three variables required in total: X, M, and Y, where X is the independent variable (IV), Y is the dependent variable (DV), and M is the (hypothesized) mediator variable that is supposed to transmit the causal effect of X to Y. The total effect of X on Y is referred to as the total effect (TE), and that effect is then partitioned into a combination of a direct effect (DE) of X on Y, and an indirect effect (IE) of X on Y that is transmitted through M. In other words, the relationship between X and Y is decomposed into a direct link and an indirect link.

While the conceptual model of mediation is straight-forward, applying it is much less so (Bullock et al., 2010). There are multiple schools of thought and discussions regarding mediation that provide detailed arguments and criteria regarding mediation claims for specific models or sets of assumptions (e.g., Baron and Kenny, 1986; Kraemer et al., 2002; Jo, 2008; Pearl, 2009; Imai et al., 2010). As still further evidence of the difficulty of making mediation claims, parameter bias, and sensitivity have emerged as common concerns (e.g., Sobel, 2008; Imai et al., 2010; VanderWeele, 2010; Fritz et al., 2016), as has statistical power for testing both indirect (e.g., Shrout and Bolger, 2002; Fritz and MacKinnon, 2007; Preacher and Hayes, 2008) and total effects (Kenny and Judd, 2014; Loeys et al., 2015; O'Rourke and MacKinnon, 2015).

Relatively untouched is that there are cross-cutting concerns related to the fact that what is considered appropriate for a mediation claim depends not only on statistical and theoretical criteria, but also on the experience, assumptions, needs, and general point of view of a researcher. Some perspectives may be more often correct than others (e.g., more tenable assumptions, better clarification of what constitutes a mediator, etc.), but all perspectives and models used by researchers are necessarily incomplete and unable to fully capture all considerations necessary for conducting research, leaving some approaches ill-suited for certain tasks. This is in line with a recent article by Gelman and Hennig (2017), who note that while the tendency in the literature is to find and formulate one best approach based on seemingly objective criteria there is nonetheless unavoidable subjectivity involved in any statistical decision. Researchers always view only a subset of reality, and rather than denying this it is advantageous—even necessary—to embrace that there are multiple perspectives relevant to any statistical discussion.

The aim of the article is not to propose new approaches or to criticize existing approaches, but to explain that the existence and use of multiple perspectives is both useful and sensible for mediation analysis. We use the term mediation in the general sense that a mediation model explains values of Y as indirectly caused by values of X, without favoring any specific statistical model or set of identifying assumptions. The three variables may be exhaustive, or a subset of much larger set of variables. As we discuss, there can be value in different and divergent considerations and convergence is not required or uniformly advantageous. Our points here are more general than any specific statistical model (and their IE, DE, and TE estimates and tests), but there are a few points that require we first review simple mediation models as estimated by ordinary least squares linear regression. We will then take the concept of mediation to an extreme with a time-series example, using the example to illustrate and discuss the various perspectives, not as a representative case but to clarify some issues.

Mediation with Linear Regression

Within a regression framework, the population parameters a, b, c, and c′ (Figures 1, 2) are estimated not with a single statistical model, but rather a set of either two or three individual regression models. We say two or three because the first, Model 1, is somewhat controversial and is not always necessary (Kenny and Judd, 2014). This model yields the sample regression weight c as an estimate of the TE:

Models 2 and 3 are used to estimate the DE and IE. Specifically, the DE is presented as the path from X to Y, c′. The IE is estimated by the product of the path from X to M (Model 2) and the path from M to Y (Model 3), i.e., the product of the regression weights a and b. The equations for these two models are as follows:

Together, these two models yield the direct effect, c′, as well as the indirect effect ab. Further, the summation of these two effects is equal to the total effect, i.e., c = c′+ab. Assuming no missing data and a saturated model (as in the case of Equations 2 and 3) this value of c is equal to that provided by Model 1.

Covariance temporal precedence and an absence of alternative explanations are all criteria for

Figure 1. Effect of X and Y without considering mediation.

Covariance temporal precedence and an absence of alternative explanations are all criteria for

Figure 2. Effect of X on Y including mediation.

The total effect can then be inferred in two different ways, either based on Figure 1 (Model 1) or on Figure 2 (a combination of Models 2 and 3), but as we will discuss there are important conceptual differences between these two numerically identical total effects. We will refer to the TE associated with Figure 1 as TE1, and the TE associated with Figure 2 as TE2.

A Time Series Example

To take the concept of mediation to an extreme, imagine a stationary autoregressive process for T equidistant time points (e.g., T consecutive days) with a lag of 1 as in the most simple autoregressive time series model, i.e., AR(1). In such a model the expected correlation between consecutive observations is stable (stationary), and the model is equivalent with a full and exclusively serial mediation model without any direct effect. X is measured at t = 1 and Y is a measured at t = T. The independent variable X has an effect on Mt= 2, which in turn has an effect on Mt= 3, and so on up to Mt= T−1 having an effect on Y at t = T. In mediation terms, there are T-2 mediators, from Mt= 2 to MT−1, with an effect only on the next mediator and finally on Y. Although this kind of mediation is an extreme case compared with the typical simple mediation model, it is nonetheless mediation in the sense that all effects are transmitted by way of an intervening effect. As a result, regardless of the time scale, the TE always equals the IE. Although extreme, such a model is a reasonable one for some time series data, e.g., it seems quite realistic that one's general mood (as distinct from ephemeral emotional states) of today mediates between one's mood of yesterday and one's mood of tomorrow. For some variables, there may be also an effect from earlier values than the previous measurement, i.e., longer lags, but such a more complex process is still a mediation process.

To help make our points more concrete we conducted a small-scale simulation. We generated data for 3, 10, 50, or 100 time points with a constant correlation of 0.10, 0.50, or 0.90 between consecutive time points, and with N = 10, 50, or 100 for each, for a total of 36 conditions. Initial time points were drawn from a standard normal distribution. We generated 500 replications per condition. All tests were done using 5,000 bootstraps and α = 0.05. These results are shown in Table 1. One can easily see that rejections of the null hypothesis for the total effect TE1 scarcely exceed the α level in nearly all conditions, which is unsurprising because of the near zero magnitude of the total effect. The only exceptions to these low rejections rates were for N = 10—but this is due to bootstrapping underestimating the standard error here for such small sample sizes—and for cases where the TE was of appreciable magnitude, i.e., for T = 3 and r = 0.5 or 0.9 or T = 10 and r = 0.9 (TE = IE = 0.25, 0.81, and 0.38742, respectively). For such large effects the TE1 is easily rejected. In contrast, the indirect effect is almost always significant, and the rejection rates are always greater than those of the TE1, even when the true size of the indirect effect is extremely small (as small as the true total effect). For nearly all cases where r = 0.5 or 0.9 the test of the IE exhibited higher power than the test of the TE1, with the minor caveat that for r = 0.5 and N = 10 the difference was minimal. In total, for 20 conditions of the 36 we considered here, rejection rates were 89–100%, with the observed power advantage for the IE relative to the TE1 as great as 94% higher (6 vs. 100%) when the TE1 is small, e.g., when T = 50 or 100. We will use this illustration to elaborate on the different perspectives on mediation, and specific aspects of the results will be focused on as necessary for the perspectives we discuss.

Covariance temporal precedence and an absence of alternative explanations are all criteria for

Table 1. Simulation results.

Five Pairs of Perspectives

Each of the five pairs of perspectives we discuss here offers a choice regarding how to view, use, and study mediation models. Each of the perspectives we discuss here has its own merits, and we do not mean to imply that any perspective or approach we discuss here is “better”—there are simply too many criteria to exhaust to evaluate such a claim, and researchers must work within the context of the problem at hand to decide what is most appropriate.

We dichotomize and treat each perspective both within and between pairs as largely independent for the purposes of explication, but there are many points of intersection and we do not wish to imply an absence of a middle ground or that each perspective from a given pair cannot be meaningfully integrated. The perspectives we discuss here are not meant to be exhaustive, and were selected because of their relevance to common topics in the mediation literature. No pair of perspectives is strictly limited to any one topic, as the various discussions regarding mediation are each better understood when looked at from multiple angles. A brief summary of each pair of perspectives we discuss is provided in Table 2, as well as a few example areas of research where the perspectives are relevant.

Covariance temporal precedence and an absence of alternative explanations are all criteria for

Table 2. Comparison of perspectives.

With vs. Without a Mediation Hypothesis

A common concern that has emerged in the mediation literature is whether or not TE1 should be required before testing indirect effects. Given that the reason researchers use mediation analysis is to test for indirect effects, whether or not there is a total effect can seem an irrelevant preliminary condition. Our time-series example is one example of why the presence of TE1 is not required for an indirect effect to be detected with a null hypothesis test, but even in more mundane cases involving three variables the IE test has greater power than the TE1 test under some parameter configurations (Rucker et al., 2011; Kenny and Judd, 2014; Loeys et al., 2015; O'Rourke and MacKinnon, 2015). Further, two competing effects can suppress each other (MacKinnon et al., 2000) such that two roughly equal (and potentially large) direct and indirect effects of opposing direction can result in a near-zero total effect. As can be seen in Table 1, a large proportion of the tests of the IE were significant even when the corresponding test of the TE1 was not significant. These are not new findings, but they illustrate that even for extremely small effect sizes such as, at the bottom of Table 1 (e.g., 1.58e-30) the IE is significant. Given a mediation hypothesis there is then no need to consider the significance of the TE1 because it is irrelevant to the presence of an IE, as the IE is estimated by different statistical models than TE1 is and a mediation hypothesis refers solely to the IE (though a more general causal relationship may be hypothesized to include both).

However, such work should not be taken as a blanket justification for testing the IE in the absence of TE1 if there is not an a priori hypothesized indirect effect. While there is great value and need for exploratory research (with later replication and validation in a separate study) and we do not wish to discourage such practices, if the XY relationship is not significant based on Model 1 then one is likely better served by staying with the null hypothesis of no relationship because of the increased risk of false positives associated with so-called “fishing expeditions” (Wagenmakers et al., 2011). Although a non-significant relationship does not exclude the possibility that there is a true and perhaps mediated relationship between X and Y—the world is full of relationships that cannot be differentiated from noise without consideration of indirect effects—a preference for parsimony and a desire to avoid false positives would suggest that one does not generate additional explanations for relationships that are not significant when first tested. Although the results shown in Table 1 show that a large proportion of indirect are significant in the absence of a significant TE1 it would not be a good idea to follow up all non-significant correlations, regression weights, F-tests, t-tests, etc. with a post-hoc mediation analysis and then attempting to explain it after the results are known (Kerr, 1998). When working with real data there are simply too many alternative explanations to consider. Absent an a priori hypothesis, the Judd and Kenny (1981) and Baron and Kenny (1986) condition requiring that the relationship between X and Y be significant makes sense.

The two perspectives represent two different and contrasting lines of reasoning and motivations—either the study is based on a mediation hypothesis or it is not. If it is, there is no preliminary condition regarding the total effect because it is irrelevant to whether or not an indirect effect may be present. It is simply necessary to conduct the appropriate test for the indirect effect. If however there was no pre-specified hypothesis, the logic of null hypothesis significance testing (NHST) requires that one stays with the conclusion of no relationship if the null hypothesis is not rejected by the data rather than conducting additional unplanned tests (with the caveat that appropriate corrections for multiple comparisons may be employed).

Specific Effects vs. Global Model

To put it colloquially, this pair of perspectives refers to whether one is interested in the forest or in the tree when investigating mediation. An effect-focused approach implies that a global model for all relationships is less important, and that one focuses instead on the tests of the effects of interest. These effects can be tested within a global statistical model (i.e., one can be interested in specific effects while still estimating all relationships), or from separate regression models. In the latter case, the global model is then primarily a conceptual one because there is not one statistical model to be used for estimation of the effects. For example, when using separate regressions the indirect effect is the product of two parameters from different statistical models, and while TE1 is an effect in one model, TE2 is a composite of two effects that stem from two separate models.

In contrast, a globally focused approach implies formulating and testing a global model for all variables, evaluating it based on relevant criteria (e.g., model fit, theoretical defensibility). The various examples of network models are examples of global models (Salter-Townshend et al., 2012), but most commonly in the social sciences global models are realized using a structural equation model approach (SEM) for the covariance of the three variables, with or without making use of any latent variables (Iacobucci et al., 2007; MacKinnon, 2008). If latent variables are used then there is the advantage of correcting for measurement error, but it is not necessary to use latent variables in a global model. Within the model, the specific mediation effect can be derived as a product of single path effects (e.g., Rijnhart et al., 2017).

The choice between, and discussions regarding, these two approaches comes with a few relevant considerations. First, there is the matter of model saturation (i.e., the same number of estimated parameters as there are variables). For the simple situation of one mediator variable and thus three variables in total, and effects described by a, b, and c′, the global model is a saturated model, and as a result the point estimate of the indirect effect is the same whether one uses different regression models or one global SEM. To some degree then the matter of specific effects vs. the global model distinction is irrelevant because simple mediation models are saturated. However, when the mediation relationships are more complex the global model is no longer necessarily a saturated model. For example, a two-mediator model is either a serial or parallel mediator model, with the former having a path between the two mediators and the latter not (Hayes, 2013). As such, a parallel two-mediator model is not saturated whereas a serial two-mediator model is. In general, from a global model perspective one would first want to test the goodness of fit of the global model, before a particular mediation effect is considered at all because the effects are conditional on the model.

Second, the power anomaly discussed in recent work reflects an effect-focused perspective based on separate regressions and vanishes when one focuses on the effect within a global statistical model, where the covariance between X and Y is simply a descriptive statistic used for model estimation and not a parameter (i.e., not a total effect to estimate). The total effect is estimated through two within-model effects. TE1 is one observed covariance among the other observed covariance measures to be explained with the model. Further, instead of two separate TE estimates (stemming from separate regressions), there is only one TE to be considered: TE2 as estimated from the model TEmodel:

Where a*, b*, and c′* are model parameters. Of course, when c′* = 0, then TESEM=a* ×b*.

Although the point estimates of TE1 and TE2 are equal for a simple mediation model, neither their associated models nor their sampling distributions are. For example, it is well known that the sampling distribution of the indirect effect estimate is skewed unless the sample size is extremely large (MacKinnon et al., 2004) and this also applies when estimated from a global model (the product of a* and b*). The skewness is inherent to the distribution of a product, and this transfers to the distribution of TE2 whether estimated based on a global model or through separate regressions. In contrast, there is no reason to expect skewness in the sampling distribution of TE1 because it is a simple parameter in Equation (2) and Figure 1, and not a product of two parameters.

The study of mediation is almost entirely effect-focused because the substantive hypotheses are mostly about particular mediation effects and their presence or not (typically defined by statistical significance), and so a global model test makes less sense from that perspective. This is particularly true because perfect model fit for the covariance of the variables is guaranteed in a simple mediation model with just the three variables X, M, and Y, despite a simple mediation model being almost certainly incomplete (Baron and Kenny, 1986; Sobel, 2008). If one is primarily interested in the effects, it further makes sense to be liberal on the model side because model constraints can lead to bias in the parameter estimates (e.g., forcing a genuine DE to be equal to 0 will bias the IE estimate) and the standard errors.

In contrast, one can expect a model testing approach to prevail in a global process theory that describes the set of variable relationships as a whole. In such a case an SEM makes more sense, and within the model one or more indirect effects are tested (e.g., van Harmelen et al., 2016). The time series example is another case where a global model approach makes sense. From an effects perspective the mediation effect for a series of 100 would be a product of 99 parameters and the direct effect would span 99 time intervals, but these would be of relatively little interest or importance. Instead it is the model that matters, and within the model the autoregressive parameter is of interest (and not the IE as a product of all these autoregressive parameters as we did for the simulation study). In a simple autoregressive model with lag 1, i.e., AR(1), a = b (and so on, depending on the number of time points), and c′ = 0. The AR(1) autoregressive model characterizes the relevant system, e.g., mood, self-esteem, etc.

As before, the two perspectives are both meaningful. One can either be interested in a global model for the relationships or one can give priority to the effects and minimize the importance of the overall model. The fewer modeling assumptions associated with an effects-perspective may lead to poorer precision and replication (e.g., larger standard errors and greater risk of overfitting), but model-based constraints are avoided. Conversely, making more assumptions leads to better precision and possibly to better replication (if the model constraints are valid). One can also make the statistical model more in line with the theoretical model in order to impose a stronger test of a theory. However, the assumptions are made at the risk of distorted parameter estimates, and the effect estimates are also conditional on the global model they belong to, which can complicate interpretation somewhat. Therefore, it can make sense to stay with separate regression analyses without a test of the global model.

Effect Size vs. Null Hypothesis Testing

Based on criticism of NHST (e.g., Kline, 2004), effect size and confidence intervals have been proposed as an alternative approach to statistical analyses (e.g., Cumming, 2012). These points have emerged in the mediation literature as well, with mediation-specific effect sizes discussed and proposed (e.g., Kraemer et al., 2008; Preacher and Kelley, 2011), and bootstrapped confidence intervals are now the standard for testing indirect effects (e.g., Shrout and Bolger, 2002; Hayes, 2013; Hayes and Scharkow, 2013).

Numerous effect size indices have been proposed for the IE, and these indices may take the form of either variance in the DV explained or in terms of the relative effects as in the case of the ratio ab/c′ (an excellent review may be found in Preacher and Kelley, 2011; note however the specific effect size proposed by these authors was later shown to be based on incorrect calculations; Wen and Fan, 2015). As it is not our intention to promote one particular measure, but rather to make a general point regarding effect size vs. null hypothesis testing perspectives, we simply use the product of the standardized a and b coefficients.

In the largest time series model illustrated previously, the indirect effect is a product of 99 terms, and as a result the expected effect size with an autoregressive coefficient of 0.90 is still a negligible 0.00003. Even so, this extremely small effect can easily lead to a rejection of the null hypothesis when the IE is tested, as illustrated in Table 1. The confidence intervals are very narrow for such a small effect, but they do not include zero. In practice, such an example would represent mediation from the NHST perspective (supported by the confidence intervals) and it could potentially be a very meaningful finding, but from the effect size perspective the effect may seem too small to be accepted or worth consideration for any practical decisions. Both points of view make sense. There is clearly mediation in the time series example, but the resulting effect is negligible in terms of the variance explained at time 100. The distance between X and Y is too large for a difference in X to make a difference for Y while in fact the underlying process is clearly a mediation process with possibly a very large magnitude from time point to time point (i.e., as small as 0.9).

As before, neither perspective is strictly superior because both perspectives have advantages and disadvantages. One possible problem when approaching mediation from the NHST perspective is that it is perhaps too attractive to look for possible mediators between X and Y after failing to reject the initial null hypothesis because of the work showing that a test of the IE has higher power, in particular given the high rates at which the TE is not rejected but the IE is as shown in Table 1 (to be clear, a strict NHST perspective would not permit such an approach, as discussed previously). Other problems are the dichotomous view on mediation (mediation vs. no mediation) while effects are in fact graded (Cumming, 2012), and the fact that rejection of the null hypothesis does not speak to how well the variance of Y is explained.

The effect size logic has its own drawbacks as well, of course. Competing indirect effects, regardless of size, can cancel each other out (note this holds true for all effects in a mediation model, e.g., a may be small because of competing effects from X to M). Another issue is that the effect size is commonly expressed in a relative way (e.g., in terms of the standard deviation of the DV or a percentage explained variance) and therefore it depends on the variance in the sample and on other factors in the study that raise questions about the appropriateness of many mediation effect sizes (Preacher and Kelley, 2011). What constitutes a relevant effect size is also not always immediately clear, as it depends immensely on the problem at hand, e.g., what the dependent variable is, how easily manipulated the independent variable(s) are, etc. A further complicating factor is that most psychological variables have arbitrary units, such as, units on a point-scale or response option numerical anchors for a questionnaire. For variables with natural units, such as, the number of deadly accidents on the road or years of life after a medical intervention, one would not need a standard deviation or a percentage of variance to express the effect size in a meaningful way.

As with the previous perspectives, these two perspectives throw light on two relevant but different aspects of the same underlying reality. The null hypothesis test is a test of a hypothesized process and whether it can be differentiated from noise, whereas the effect size and confidence intervals tell us how large the result of the process is and what the width of the uncertainty is. Not all processes have results of a substantial size—and this is clear in the time-series example we showed previously—but even an extremely small effect can be meaningful as the indication of a process.

Directness vs. Indirectness

Another pair of perspectives depends upon the semantics of causality. In both linguistics (e.g., Shibatani, 2001) and in law (e.g., Hart and Honore, 1985), directness is an enhancer of causal interpretation, and a remote cause is considered less of a cause or even no cause at all. In contrast, in the psychological literature a causal interpretation is supported when there is evidence for an intermediate psychological or biological process and thus for some indirectness. Causality claims seem supported if one can specify through which path the causality flows.

From the directness perspective, a general concern is that temporal distance allows for additional, unconsidered (e.g., unmodeled) effects to occur, and so the TE is emphasized. Regardless of the complexity of a model, a model is always just a model and by definition it does not capture all aspects of the variable relationships (Edwards, 2013). In reality there are always intervening events such that with increasing time between measurements the chances are higher that unknown events are the proper causes of the dependent variable, rather than the mediator(s). Though a full discussion is too complex to engage in here, a similar view has been taken by philosophers such as, Woodwarth (2003). The inclusion of a mediator necessarily increases the minimum distance between X and Y, and the associated paths are necessarily correlational and require additional model assumptions, and if these assumptions do not hold then the estimates of the IE and DE are biased (Sobel, 2008). Additionally, one can manipulate X but not M at the same time without likely interfering with the proposed mediation process and thus potentially destroying it, and so the link between M and Y remains a correlational one.

Network models are an interesting example of an indirectness perspective on causation, and one that is taken to a relative extreme. In such models, a large number of variables cause one another, and possibly mutually so, e.g., insomnia may result in concentration difficulties and then work problems, which may then aggravate the insomnia due to excess worry, before ultimately resulting in a depressed state (Borsboom and Cramer, 2013). Another example of an indirectness perspective can be found in relation to climate change: Lakoff (2012) posted an interesting discussion and introduced the term “systemic causation” for causation in a network with chains of indirect causation. Many mediation models one can find in the psychological literature would qualify for the label of systemic causation, both in terms of the model (e.g., multiple connected mediators) and in terms of the underlying processes (e.g., changes in neurotransmitters underlying changes in behavior). Somewhat akin to the effect vs. model testing perspectives, if the additional statistical and theoretical assumptions hold then the benefit is a fuller and more precise picture of the variable relationships, but if they do not then statistical analyses will yield biased estimates and the inferences drawn made suspect.

The two perspectives make sense for the example application from the simulation study. From the directness perspective, as the number of time points increases it becomes increasingly difficult to claim that X has a causal effect on Y. It is easy to make such claims for T = 3, but for a large number of time points such as, T = 50 or 100, claims of causation are most relevant to the mediators most proximal to Y (alternatively, to those shortly following X). In contrast, for the indirectness perspective, a systems interpretation of causality makes perfect sense for time series. The autoregressive process does have causal relevance, and the identification of such a long chain of effects would likely be considered compelling evidence of causation.

Thus, indirectness and distance make a causal interpretation stronger from one perspective, whereas they make a causal interpretation less convincing from another perspective. These two perspectives are not in direct contradiction—they simply focus on different aspects of the same reality and reflect different needs and concerns. In the case of directness, the criterion is a minimizing ambiguity about whether or not there is an effect of X on Y. In contrast, in the case of adopting an indirectness perspective, the primary criterion is maximizing information about the process and thus about intermediate steps because it makes the causal process more understandable.

Hypothesized vs. Alternative Explanations

Our final pair of perspectives refers to whether one is primarily interested in a confirmatory test of a mediation hypothesis about the relationship between two variables or whether one would rather test one or more other explanations that would undermine a mediation claim. Loosely, the difference between these two perspectives is that the former focuses on showing that a mediation explanation is appropriate, and the latter focuses on showing that alternative explanations are not.

In practice this distinction can be a subtle one, as it is always necessary to control for confounders, but there are considerable differences in the information acquired and required for these two perspectives, as well as the amount of effort invested and what is attended to Rouder et al. (2016).

For mediation, researchers generally work with a theory-derived mediation hypothesis and collect data that allows them to test the null hypothesis of no mediation. It is a search for a well-defined form of information, and further the search is considered complete when that information is obtained. If the null hypothesis of no relationship is rejected, the mediation claim is considered to be supported and the case closed. If it is not rejected, explanations are generated as to why the study failed, and the hypothesis is tested again (ideally in a separate study, but this also manifests as including unplanned covariates in the statistical models). Alternative explanations are often not generated or tested if the null hypothesis of mediation is rejected. This is an intriguing asymmetry between the two possible outcomes of a study—supportive results are accepted, unsupportive results are retested.

A somewhat different approach is to formulate alternative explanations for a significant effect that are in conflict with a mediation claim. The simplest and most common means of doing this is to include additional covariates in Models 2 and 3 that are competing explanations for the relationships between the three variables, or to experimentally manipulate these explanations as well. In cases where temporal precedence is not clear such as, in observational data or when there are only two time points, it is also useful to consider alternative variable orders, e.g., treating X as M or M as Y. Another approach is to assume that there are unmeasured confounders that bias the estimates and necessitate examining parameter sensitivity (VanderWeele, 2010). Still another is to test the proposed mediator as a moderator instead (a distinction which is itself often unclear; Kraemer et al., 2008) or as a hierarchical effect (Preacher et al., 2010).

Referring to the time series example, it was simply a test of an autoregressive model with a single lag and the power to detect such small effects in a constrained serial mediation model, but in practice it would also make sense to consider a moving-average model, where the value of an observation depends on the mean of the variable and on a coefficient associated with the error term (Brockwell and Davis, 2013). Loosely, the residuals might “cause” the values of subsequent time points, and are not simply measurement errors but new and unrelated inputs specific for the time point in question.

As with each previous pair of perspectives, both perspectives have advantages and disadvantages. Focusing on confirmation has the general advantages of simplicity and expediency by utilizing past research to direct future research, with a relatively clearly defined set of criteria for what counts as supporting evidence. There are also cases where it is not necessary to exhaust all alternatives, and instead simplicity and sufficiency of an explanation are valued more strongly. However, this perspective comes with the risk of increased false-positives and a narrow search for explanations for relationships between variables because what is considered is determined in part by what is easy to consider. Finding that one explanation works does not prove there are no other—and possibly better—explanations, and a model is always just a model (Edwards, 2013).

Focusing on competing hypotheses has the advantage of potentially providing stronger evidence for a mediation claim by way of providing evidence that competing hypotheses are not appropriate. Conversely, when a competing hypothesis cannot be ruled out easily, it may turn out to be a better explanation than a mediation model upon further research. However, there are a few very strong limitations regarding competing evidence. The first is that for every explanation, there are an infinite number of competing explanations that are all equally capable of describing a covariance matrix. Some are ignorable due to their sheer absurdity, but there are still an infinite number of reasonable alternative explanations (for example, it is easy to generate a very long list of explanations for why self-esteem and happiness correlate) and criteria for evaluating these explanations are often unclear or extremely difficult to satisfy. Further, it is often impossible to estimate alternative statistical models because of the limited information provided by only a small set of variables (e.g., factors are difficult to estimate with a small number of indicators). Similarly, estimating a very large number of complicated interacting variable relationships may require sample sizes that are not realistic.

A Note Regarding Philosophical Considerations

Before turning to our discussion, we wish to note that philosophical views on causality differ with respect to whether a total effect is implied or necessary, and that there is substantial overlap between the philosophical views and our discussion of directness vs. indirectness distinction. We rely on a chapter by Psillos (2009) in the Oxford Handbook of Causality for a brief discussion of philosophical views, but see White (1990) for an introduction for psychologists.

In Humean regularity theories, X is a cause if it is regularly followed by Y. This suggests a total effect as a condition for X being a cause of Y. In a deductive-nomological view attributed to Hempel and Oppenheim, for X to be a cause it needs to be connected to Y through one or more laws so that X is sufficient for Y. Sufficiency would again imply a total effect, albeit possibly a very small one, because there may be multiple sufficient conditions. Only when a condition is at the same time sufficient and necessary can one expect a clear relationship.

Another view is formulated in the complex regularity view of Mackie (1974) and his INUS conditions. According to this view a cause is an Insufficient but Non-redundant part of a condition which is itself Unnecessary but Sufficient for the effect. In other words, a cause is a term (e.g., A) in a conjunctive bundle (e.g., A and B and C), and there can be many such conjunctive bundles that are each sufficient for the effect. This expression is called the disjunctive normal form (e.g., Y if and only if A and B and C or D and E or F and G or H or I). This form does not imply a total effect of X on Y (e.g., A as X), because the disjunctive normal form may be highly complex and may therefore not lead to X and Y being correlated, while X is still accepted as a cause because it is part of that form. In other words, the relationship between a cause and the event to be explained is such that a cause can occur either with or without the event and vice versa. The INUS view is consistent with indirectness and systemic causation, whereas Humean regularity theory is better in agreement with directness of causes.

Discussion

From the above discussion of the various perspectives we wish to conclude that there is not just one way to look at mediation. Researchers may approach mediation with or without an a priori hypothesis, or may focus on either a global model or a specific effect that derives either from the global model or that is estimated from separate regression analyses. A researcher may value directness or indirectness as causal evidence, or may prefer effect-focused or significance-focused tests. Researchers may further focus on hypothesized or competing alternative explanations when testing for mediation. Each pair of perspectives has associated advantages and disadvantages, and which is to be preferred depends on the nature of a given study or topic of interest.

The perspectives we have discussed here do not exhaust all common perspectives. Another common pair is a practical vs. a theoretical goal for testing a mediation claim. The aim of a mediation study can either be to find ways to change the level of the dependent variable, or the aim can be to understand the process through which the independent variable affects the dependent variable, or the purpose of the research may be prediction. Mediation can help to understand a process and advance a theoretical goal even when the total effect is negligible, but from a practical point of view, mediation is not helpful for such a case unless there is an easily addressed suppression effect or Y represents an important outcome such as, death. For applied settings where affecting change by way of an intervention of some sort, a direct effect or an unsuppressed large indirect effect is in general much more useful.

Another example is that the concept of mediation remains somewhat ambiguous despite the clarification provided by Baron and Kenny (1986). That mediation explains the relationship between X and Y can mean two things: (1) Mediation explains values of Y as indirectly caused by values of X. (2) Mediation causes the relationship between X and Y. Following the second interpretation, the relationship itself (or absence of relationship) is explained by values of M. Here, we have interpreted the concept of mediation in the first sense. Note that the second way of understanding mediation is also commonly considered to be moderation, where M is supposed to explain why there sometimes is a relationship between X and Y and sometimes there is not (or why the strength of the relationship varies). The MacArthur approach provides some clarification regarding the latter sense (the approach is named after a foundation; Kraemer et al., 2002, 2008), and notably it adds an interaction term between X and M to Model 3. The approach specifies that if X precedes M, there is an association between X and M, and there is either an interaction between X and M or a main effect of M on Y then M is said to mediate Y. In contrast, if there is an interaction between X and M, but no main effect of M on Y, then X is said to moderate M. In short, the approach specifies that a statistical interaction can still reflect mediation (see also Muller et al., 2005; Preacher et al., 2007). The approach further focuses on effect sizes over NHST, and states that causal inferences should not be drawn from observational data for reasons similar to those we provide in the discussion of the hypothesized vs. alternative explanations section. The approach also explicitly treats the indirect effect as only potentially causal, arguing that the Baron and Kenny approach to mediation and moderation can potentially bias the search for explanations because of its assumption that the causal process is already known but must only be tested. The MacArthur approach then seems to favor (or is at least mindful of) some of the specific perspectives we have discussed here, and it remains to be seen what the impact is of the approach on mediation and moderation practice and theory.

We have discussed mediation at a rather abstract, general level, and some of the details of the different perspectives we have discussed here are not always relevant to specific statistical analyses. In keeping with common practices we have utilized parametric mean and covariance-based approaches for our discussion, but median-based approaches to mediation have been proposed (e.g., Yuan and MacKinnon, 2014), and for such approaches the notion of global model testing by way of comparing the fit of different SEMs is largely irrelevant in a frequentist framework (though it may be done within a Bayesian framework; Wang et al., 2016). For network analysis, the strong focus on indirectness of effects within a larger system with a very large number of variables that each may be treated as X, M, or Y, renders the issue of a specific mediation hypothesis or a total effect irrelevant.

On the other hand, while we have discussed each perspective as independent views, there are obvious intersections between them and ample reasons to adopt the opposing perspective in some cases, or even both for the same study. For example, when working with a global model, specific effects within the model vary in how trustworthy they may be considered. Those effects that are considered less trustworthy can be interpreted more from a directness perspective because of the ambiguity regarding their effects, and those that are uncontroversial can be interpreted from an indirectness perspective. Confidence intervals and NHST also make use of the same information and if interpreted dichotomously (reject vs. not reject) the results will not differ. There are also intersections across pairs as well, e.g., testing competing explanations is facilitated by adopting a global model-focused approach, and the issue competing explanations in general provides much of the rationale for preferring a directness perspective on causation.

We wish to include a cautionary note concerning causality before concluding. A mediation hypothesis is a causal hypothesis (James and Brett, 1984), but we realize that a causal relationship is difficult if not impossible to prove in general, let alone in the complex world of the social sciences (Brady, 2008). Further, the statistical models used to test mediation are not inherently causal—they are simply predictive or descriptive, and the b path is necessarily correlational (Sobel, 2008). That the data are in line with the hypothesis and even that several alternative explanations can be eliminated does not prove causality. It does not follow from the combination of the two premises “If A then B” (if M mediates then the null hypothesis of no indirect effect is rejected) and “B is the case” (null hypothesis rejected) that “A is the case.” (M mediates; i.e., the fallacy known as affirming the consequent). Instead, modus tollens (i.e., “B is not the case”) is a valid argument for the absence of A, so that one may want to believe that A is ruled out in the absence of B. Although the reasoning is logically correct, the problem with mediation analysis is that “B is not the case” in practice is simply a probabilistic non-rejection of a null hypothesis and does not directly implicate the truth of any other claim.

Conclusion

Human behavior and psychology emerges from dynamic and complicated systemic effects that are impossible to capture completely, and researchers choose what must be understood for a given problem—what fraction of the network of interacting variables is most relevant—and so which perspective to adopt. Ultimately, mediation analysis is simply a tool used for describing, discovering, and testing possible causal relationships. How the tool is used (or not used) and what information is most relevant depends on the problem to be solved and the question to be answered.

Author Contributions

RA was responsible for most of the writing, in particular any revisions and the introduction and discussion. PD provided most of the core points involved in the discussion of each perspective.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Baron, R. M., and Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator-mediator variable distinction in social psychological research: conceptual, strategic, and statistical considerations. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 51, 1175–1182. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.51.6.1173

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Borsboom, D., and Cramer, A. O. (2013). Network analysis: an integrative approach to the structure of psychopathology. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 9, 91–121. doi: 10.1146/annurev-clinpsy-050212-185608

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brady, H. E. (2008). Causation and Explanation in Social Science. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Brockwell, P. J., and Davis, R. A. (2013). Time Series: Theory and Methods. New York, NY: Springer-Verlag.

Google Scholar

Cumming, G. (2012). Understanding the New Statistics: Effect Sizes, Confidence Intervals, and Meta-Analysis. New York, NY: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Edwards, M. C. (2013). Purple unicorns, true models, and other things i've never seen. Meas. Interdiscipl. Res. Perspect. 11, 107–111. doi: 10.1080/15366367.2013.835178

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fritz, M. S., Kenny, D. A., and MacKinnon, D. P. (2016). The combined effects of measurement error and omitting confounders in the single mediator model. Multivariate Behav. Res. 51, 681–697. doi: 10.1080/00273171.2016.1224154

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gelman, A., and Hennig, C. (2017). Beyond subjective and objective in statistics. J. R. Stat. Soc. 180, 1–31. doi: 10.1111/rssa.12276

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hart, H. L. A., and Honore, A. M. (1985). Causation in the Law. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Google Scholar

Hayes, A. F. (2013). Introduction to Mediation, Moderation, and Conditional Process Analysis: A Regression-Based Approach. New York, NY: Guilford.

Hayes, A. F., and Scharkow, M. (2013). The relative trustworthiness of inferential tests of the indirect effect in statistical mediation analysis: does method really matter? Psychol. Sci. 24, 1918–1927. doi: 10.1177/0956797613480187

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Iacobucci, D., Saldanha, N., and Deng, X. (2007). A meditation on mediation: evidence that structural equation models perform better than regressions. J. Consum. Psychol. 17, 140–154. doi: 10.1016/S1057-7408(07)70020-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Imai, K., Keele, L., and Yamamoto, T. (2010). Identification, inference and sensitivity analysis for causal mediation effects. Stat. Sci. 25, 51–71. doi: 10.1214/10-STS321

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

James, L. R., and Brett, J. M. (1984). Mediators, moderators, and tests for mediation. J. Appl. Psychol. 69, 307–321. doi: 10.1037/0021-9010.69.2.307

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Judd, C. M., and Kenny, D. A. (1981). Process analysis: estimating mediation in treatment evaluation. Eval. Rev. 5, 602–619. doi: 10.1177/0193841X8100500502

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kline, R. B. (2004). Beyond Significance Testing. Reforming Data Analysis Methods in Behavioral Research. Washington DC: APA Books.

Kraemer, H. C., Kiernan, M., Essex, M., and Kupfer, D. J. (2008). How and why criteria defining moderators and mediators differ between the Baron & Kenny and MacArthur approaches. Health Psychol. 27, 101–108. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.27.2(Suppl.).S101

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kraemer, H. C., Wilson, G. T., Fairburn, C. G., and Agras, W. S. (2002). Mediators and moderators of treatment effects in randomized clinical trials. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 59, 877–883. doi: 10.1001/archpsyc.59.10.877

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Loeys, T., Moerkerke, B., and Vansteelandt, S. (2015). A cautionary note on the power of the test for the indirect effect in mediation analysis. Front. Psychol. 5:1549. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01549

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mackie, J. L. (1974). The Cement of the Universe. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Pres.

Google Scholar

MacKinnon, D. (2008). Introduction to Statistical Mediation Analysis. New York, NY: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Google Scholar

MacKinnon, D. P., Lockwood, C. M., and Williams, J. (2004). Confidence limits for the indirect effect. Distribution of the product and resampling methods. Multivariate Behav. Res. 39, 99–128. doi: 10.1207/s15327906mbr3901_4

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

O'Rourke, H. P., and MacKinnon, D. P. (2015). When the test of mediation is more powerful than the test of the total effect. Behav. Res. Methods, 47:424. doi: 10.3758/s13428-014-0481-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Preacher, K. J., and Hayes, A. F. (2008). Asymptotic and resampling strategies for assessing and comparing indirect effects in multiple mediator models. Behav. Res. Methods 40, 879–891. doi: 10.3758/BRM.40.3.879

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Preacher, K. J., and Kelley, K. (2011). Effect measures for mediation models. Quantitative strategies for communication indirect effects. Psychol. Methods 16, 93–115. doi: 10.1037/a0022658

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Preacher, K. J., Rucker, D. D., and Hayes, A. F. (2007). Addressing moderated mediation hypotheses: theory, methods, and prescriptions. Multivariate Behav. Res. 42, 185–227. doi: 10.1080/00273170701341316

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Psillos, S. (2009). “Regularity theories,” in Oxford Handbook of Causation, eds H. Bebee, P. Menzies, and C. Hitchcock (New York, NY: Oxford University Press), 131–157.

Google Scholar

Rijnhart, J. J., Twisk, J. W., Chinapaw, M. J., de Boer, M. R., and Heymans, M. W. (2017). Comparison of methods for the analysis of relatively simple mediation models. Contemp. Clin. Trials Commun. 7, 130–135. doi: 10.1016/j.conctc.2017.06.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rouder, J. N., Morey, R. D., Verhagen, J., Province, J. M., and Wagenmakers, E. J. (2016). Is there a free lunch in inference?. Top. Cogn. Sci. 8, 520–547. doi: 10.1111/tops.12214

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rucker, D. D., Preacher, K. J., Tormala, Z. L., and Petty, R. E. (2011). Mediation analysis in social psychology: current practices and new recommendations. Soc. Pers. Psychol. Compass 5, 359–371. doi: 10.1111/j.1751-9004.2011.00355.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Salter-Townshend, M., White, A., Gollini, I., and Murphy, T. B. (2012). Review of statistical network analysis: models, algorithms, and software. Statist. Anal. Data Mining 5, 243–264. doi: 10.1002/sam.11146

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Shibatani, M. (2001). “Some basic issues in the grammar of causation,” in Grammar of Causation and Interpersonal Manipulation, ed M. Shibatani (Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins Publishing Company), 1–22.

Shrout, P. E., and Bolger, N. (2002). Mediation in experimental and nonexperimental studies: new procedures and recommendations. Psychol. Methods 7, 422–455. doi: 10.1037/1082-989X.7.4.422

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sobel, M. E. (2008). Identification of causal parameters in randomized studies with mediating variables. J. Educ. Behav. Stat. 33, 230–251. doi: 10.3102/1076998607307239

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

van Harmelen, A. L., Gibson, J. L., St Clair, M. C., Owens, M., Brodbeck, J., Dunn, V., et al. (2016). Friendships and family support reduce subsequent depressive symptoms in at-risk adolescents. PLoS ONE 11:e0153715. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0153715

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wagenmakers, E. J., Wetzels, R., Borsboom, D., and Van Der Maas, H. L. (2011). Why psychologists must change the way they analyze their data: the case of psi: comment on Bem (2011). J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 100, 426–432. doi: 10.1037/a0022790

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wang, Y., Feng, X. N., and Song, X. Y. (2016). Bayesian quantile structural equation models. Struct. Equ. Model. Multidiscipl. J. 23, 246–258. doi: 10.1080/10705511.2015.1033057

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

White, P. (1990). Ideas about causation in philosophy and psychology. Psychol. Bull. 108, 3–18. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.108.1.3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Woodwarth, J. (2003). Making Things Happen. A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

What are the three criteria for causation?

The first three criteria are generally considered as requirements for identifying a causal effect: (1) empirical association, (2) temporal priority of the indepen- dent variable, and (3) nonspuriousness. You must establish these three to claim a causal relationship.

What is covariance temporal precedence and?

Covariance: significant relationships help establish covariance. When 2 variables are significantly correlated there is covariance. 2. Temporal precedence: Because each variable is measured in at least two different points in time, they know which one came first.

What is temporal precedence criterion?

in establishing cause–effect relationships between two variables, the principle that the cause must be shown to have occurred before the effect. Two other requirements are those of covariation and nonspuriousness (i.e., there are no plausible alternative explanations for the observed relationship).

What are the 3 criteria for establishing a causal relationship quizlet?

Covariance (association between variables).
Temporal Order (IV done before DV).
No alternative explanations (confounds are ruled out).